Liberal Intergovernmentalism

Print   

23 Mar 2015

Disclaimer:
This essay has been written and submitted by students and is not an example of our work. Please click this link to view samples of our professional work witten by our professional essay writers. Any opinions, findings, conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of EssayCompany.

What choice for Europe? Reflections on agency and structure in Liberal Intergovernmentalism

ABSTRACT

This article examines how the relationship between agency and structure is dealt with in Liberal Intergovernmentalism, a prevailing theory of European integration. It demonstrates that, contrary to the widespread view that it is agency-centred, Liberal Intergovernmentalism is in fact a highly structuralist theory in the issue areas it claims to explain best. In these areas integration is ultimately explained in terms of developments in economic structures, leaving no room for agency and ideas. The article also shows that, despite the importance it ascribes to changes in economic structures, Liberal Intergovernmentalism fails to theorise their possible causes.

Keywords:

Liberal Intergovernmentalism; Moravcsik; Agency; Structure; Integration theory

Over the past two decades Andrew Moravcsik's Liberal Intergovernmentalism (LI) has established itself as one of the prevailing theories of European integration. Elegantly combining a liberal theory of preference formation with an intergovernmentalist theory of interstate bargains and a functional theory of institutional choice it explains European integration as the outcome of a series of intergovernmental negotiations. More than any other contemporary theory of integration LI and its application in empirical analyses has provoked discussion in the field of EU studies. Opinions are divided between those who admire LI for its parsimony and predictive power and those who feel that its account of regional integration misses out on too much of importance. Either way, hardly anyone would dispute that it continues to be a theory that it is necessary to relate to in one way or another in theoretically informed work on European integration.

The purpose of this article is to critically examine the liberal intergovernmentalist explanation of integration from a meta-theoretical perspective. More precisely, it will be systematically analysed how the relationship between agency and structure is dealt with in LI. Any theory's account of the social world, or delimited parts of it, is based on a particular, albeit often implicit, conceptualisation of the agency-structure relationship - and whether or not this conceptualisation is convincing impacts greatly on the quality of the theory's account of social phenomena and change. There is thus much to be learned about a theory, in this case LI, from examining its underlying assumptions with respect to agency and structure. This is even more so because appearances can be deceiving: as it will be argued in this article, LI which appears and is widely assumed to offer an agency-centred account of European integration, turns out to do the opposite on closer scrutiny.

In addition to this introduction and a conclusion the article is divided into seven sections. The first two sections set the stage for later analyses by briefly introducing LI and the question of the agency-structure relationship, while also accounting for their respective significance. The following three sections examine how the agency-structure question is dealt with at each of the three stages of LI: preference formation, interstate bargaining and institutional choice. Against this background section six critically examines the liberal intergovernmentalist explanation of European integration before section seven discusses the political implications of LI.

1. Liberal Intergovernmentalism

Andrew Moravcsik's Liberal intergovernmentalism (LI) was first presented in the early 1990s and later elaborated and applied in a string of publications of which the monumental book The Choice for Europe (1998) contains the most detailed exposition and test of the theory. LI is presented as a framework for synthesising theories into a coherent account of regional integration. The latter is explained as the result of ‘a series of celebrated intergovernmental bargains' (Moravcsik, 1993: 473). More precisely integration is seen as the outcome of a three-stage process where: (1) national interests or goals arise in the context of domestic politics; (2) governments bargain with each other to further their national interest; and (3) governments make an institutional choice to secure credible commitment once a substantive agreement has been reached.

LI quickly became a focal point in debates on how to theorise European integration and it has subsequently kept this position. According to Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig (2009: 67), LI ‘has acquired the status of a “baseline theory” in the study of regional integration: an essential first cut explanation against which other theories are often compared'. In their view, ‘it has achieved this dominant status due to its theoretical soundness, empirical power, and utility as a foundation for synthesis with other explanations' (2009: 67). To be sure, not everyone would agree with this latter sentiment. As alluded to in the introduction, several scholars have criticised the theory for painting a too incomplete or even misleading picture of the European integration process and the ‘empirical power' of the resulting analyses has often been questioned (e.g. Diez, 1999; Smith, 2000; Wincott, 1995; see also Cini, 2007: 112-14 for an overview of some critiques of LI). Inasmuch as relatively few scholars besides Moravcsik appear to wholeheartedly embrace LI (Pollack, 2001; however, cf. Laursen, 2002), it is probably fair to say that it has acquired its status as a “baseline theory” as much because of its perceived weaknesses as because of its strengths.

Similar to Waltz's (1979) neorealism LI is a parsimonious and bold theory that lends itself to accusations of neglecting or underestimating the significance of important parameters - in the case of LI for instance transnational business groups and activist supranational institutions. Indeed, LI does this deliberately, seeking ‘to simplify EU politics, stressing the essential and excluding certain secondary activities' (Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig, 2009: 68). Hereby it follows the neo-positivist recipe for theory construction, according to which theories should take the form of simplified models that can support efforts to make generalisations by singling out as few variables as possible and account for the causal relations between, and the relative weight of, these variables. Falsifiable hypothesises are derived from such theories and subsequently tested against reliable empirical data. On the basis of such tests, theories can then be further refined or occasionally discarded. (1)

Testing LI is precisely what Moravcsik sets out to do in The Choice for Europe. Here standardised hypotheses derived from LI and competing (albeit for the most part artificial) theories are tested against an overwhelming amount of empirical data in five cases studies. Needless to say, LI comes out on top as the theory with the by far greatest explanatory power. More generally, The Choice for Europe constitutes an example par excellence of research informed by neo-positivist methods and standards. In its early pages Moravcsik informs his readership that the book ‘eschews ad hoc explanation and seeks instead to discover what is generalizable about EC history' (1998: 2) and that it ‘is based on methods which, while far from ideal, generate more rigorous, transparent, objective, and reliable tests of competing theoretical claims about European integration than have heretofore been conducted' (1998: 10). The bulk of studies of EC decision-making are criticised for biased data selection and for relying on ‘citations to secondary sources themselves drawn from journalistic commentary or still other secondary sources' (1998: 10). In contrast to this, Moravcsik claims to have backed ‘potentially controversial attribution of motive or strategy … by “hard” primary sources (direct evidence of decision-making) rather than “soft” or secondary sources' (1998: 10, see also pp. 80-84). (2)

2. Agency and structure

The question of how to conceptualise the relationship between agency and structure is arguably one of the most important questions facing social scientists (Archer, 1995: 65). This is due to the importance of agency and structures in the social world and to the fact that it is impossible to offer explanations of events in the social world without appealing to some understanding of their relationship. As mentioned in the introduction there is thus much to be learned about the nature and quality of substantive theories from examining their underlying assumptions with respect to this relationship. Yet the way the latter is dealt with is also important for political reasons, to which we will come back in section 7 below. “Agency” denotes the ability of agents, whether individuals or groups, to act upon situations and it ‘implies a sense of free will, choice or autonomy - that the actor could have behaved differently' (Hay, 2002: 94). Agency should thus not be confused with concepts like “individuals”, “actors” or “agents”: without anticipating the conclusions of this article too much, a theory can refer to plenty of agents, while not allowing for any agency. “Structure”, on the other hand, refers to the relational context within which agents operate. Structures define the range of options available to agents.

Nowadays the vast majority of scholars agree that both agency and structure matter: phenomena and developments in the social world issue not from either one or the other but are a product of both. If this is the case then it is necessary to break with the two ways of conceptualising the relation between agency and structure that have traditionally been dominant within social theory, namely structuralism and individualism. In their pure versions these positions either picture agents as marionettes (structuralism) or as omnipotent puppet-masters (individualism) (Archer, 1995; XXXXX). However, knowing that both agency and structure matter does not in itself take us far. To make a difference the insight needs to be incorporated into substantive theories and this is by no means an easy task. This contributes to explain why many theories end up offering reductionist explanations of the specific social phenomena they are meant to render intelligible.

In the discipline of International Relations (IR) a debate over the “agent-structure problem” was initiated in the late 1980s by scholars such as Wendt (1987) and Hollis and Smith (1990). Later, and certainly no less interesting contributions to this debate included Doty (1997), Bieler and Morton (2001) and Wight (2006). The debate has done much to clarify and in many cases criticise the ontological and epistemological assumptions underlying mainstream IR theories, particularly Waltzian neorealism (Waltz, 1979). In EU Studies a similar debate has not taken place, and although in particular some constructivist scholars, have taken an interest in the agency-structure relationship (e.g. Wind, 2001), a comprehensive study of the way the most important theories of European integration and governance deal with it has yet to be published. However, it seems to be a widespread view among EU scholars that many of these theories privilege agency over structure. For instance, Risse (2004: 161) writes that the ‘prevailing theories of European integration - whether neofunctionalism, liberal intergovernmentalism, or “multi-level governance” - are firmly committed to a rationalist ontology which is agency-centred by definition'. In a similar vein, other scholars have noticed ‘the ahistorical and structure-blind assumptions' underlying intergovernmentalism (Hix, 1994: 9) and observed that in LI ‘agents are, implicitly or explicitly, considered primary - actors ultimately determine the shape of overall structures' (Christiansen, 1998: 103). In the next sections, the validity of this widespread view will be examined through an analysis of the way the agency-structure relationship is dealt with at each of the three stages in LI.

3. National preference formation

The first stage in explaining the outcome of intergovernmental bargains is to account for the national preferences, which are defined as ‘an ordered and weighted set of values placed on future substantive outcomes … that might result from international political interaction' (Moravcsik, 1998: 24). This is done by means of a liberal political economy theory of preference formation, according to which national preferences arise in the context of domestic politics, where national government leaders form them on the basis of the preferences and actions of the most important societal groups. Most important among these are domestic producers: ‘The systematic political bias in favor of existing producer groups and against those, notably consumers, taxpayers, third-country producers, and also potential future producers, stems from the former's more intense, certain, and institutionally represented and organized interests' (1998: 36). The state is conceptualised as ‘a representative institution constantly subject to capture and recapture ... by societal groups' (Moravcsik, 1997: 518). Because governments have an interest in remaining in office, they need the support from coalitions of domestic actors. The policies pursued by governments are ‘therefore constrained by the underlying identities, interests, and power of individuals and groups … who constantly pressure the central decision makers to pursue politics consistent with their preferences' (ibid: 518). In other words, ‘[g]roups articulate preferences; governments aggregate them' and it is through this process that ‘the set of national interests or goals that states bring to international negotiations' emerges (Moravcsik, 1993: 483).

To evaluate the way the agency-structure relationship is dealt with at this stage in LI it is clearly crucial to understand the origins of the preferences of societal groups. Some of the early critics of LI suggested that the theory fails to account adequately for this. For instance, it was pointed out that ‘the origins of such interests are exogenized' (Risse-Kappen, 1996: 56) while others claimed that in LI ‘interests are not structurally derived' (Caporaso and Keeler, 1995: 44) and even that they ‘emerge mysteriously' (McSweeney, 1998: 101). Had it in fact been the case that LI leaves completely open the question of where the preferences of societal groups come from it would have allowed for an agency-centred perspective on preference formation. That is, preferences could have been formed on the basis of all sorts of ideas and individual inclinations. However, this would have seriously undermined the parsimony and explanatory power of the theory and hence it was in fact never left open where preferences come from. As Moravcsik has made clear, LI perceives preferences to be directly caused by structural circumstances, more precisely economic structures:

‘I employ a structural theory of those preferences. My structural approach…employs trade flows, competitiveness, inflation rates, and other data to predict what the economic preferences of societal actors - and therefore governments - should be' (Moravcsik, 1999b: 377).

In other words, economic preferences are derived from economic structures: societal groups organise and articulate their preferences ‘on the basis of calculations of net expected costs and benefits resulting from the introduction of new policies' (Moravcsik, 1993: 489). It follows as a logical implication that ‘shifts in preferences should follow the onset and precede the resolution of shifts or trends in economic circumstances' (Moravcsik, 1998: 50).

The assumption that economic structures translate directly into specific preferences is made possible by the rationality assumption underpinning LI. The widespread view that LI is agency-centred is related to this assumption that individuals, groups, governments and even states are rational. This begs the question of what “rationalism” precisely entails, especially as some scholars have suggested that Moravcsik fails to spell this clearly out (Christiansen et al., 2001: 4). In a recent piece Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig (2009: 68) put it as follows:

‘Rationalism is an individualist or agency assumption. Actors calculate the alternative courses of action and choose the one that maximizes (or satisfies) their utility under the circumstances. Collective outcomes are explained as the result of aggregated individual actions based on efficient pursuit - albeit subject to the information at hand and uncertainty about the future'.

Despite the qualifications at the end of the quote it is clear that whatever this uncertainty pertains to it is not to the consequences of the actions of agents: agents are assumed to be very well-informed about these because, as Moravcsik has put it himself, in ‘a world in which the future consequences of actions are unknown … LI would make little sense' (1995: 626). This is an important manifestation, because the more it is assumed that agents know the future consequences of their actions, the more it must also be assumed that they are fully informed about the context in which they currently find themselves. It is quite simply logically inconceivable that an agent can somehow know the future consequences of his or her actions without having perfect or very close to perfect information at hand at the moment of the action itself. Moravcsik is thus significantly underplaying the strength of his rationality assumption when stating that ‘it takes no position on whether states are fully informed, though a framework in which states are assumed to be informed generally performs well' (1998: 23). Why not walk the plank? Surely states and other agents can safely be assumed to be blessed full information if it has already been established that no or very few unintended consequences will follow from their actions?

At the end of the day the rationality assumption boils down to the view that agents are utility-maximisers with clearly ordered preferences who are (almost?) fully informed, also about the future consequences of actions. However, it should not be concluded from this that LI is an agency-centred theory as the conventional wisdom has it. As we have seen above, preferences are derived from economic structures - not just in the weak sense that structures are important in relation to preferences but in the strong sense that they alone dictate preferences (albeit with a minor qualification to which we will return in a moment). Because the rational agents are assumed to be so well-informed their actions become predictable once their structural environment has been mapped. Indeed, only structures matter here inasmuch as ‘[p]references are by definition causally independent of the strategies of other actors' (Moravcsik, 1997: 519, see also 1998: 24-25).

Moreover, ideas are for the most part not allowed to play any role in relation to preference formation. It is worth dwelling on this for a moment. On one hand, Moravcsik does not hesitate to acknowledge the importance of ideas, as when he proclaims that they ‘...are like oxygen or language; it is essentially impossible for humans to function without them' (Moravcsik, 2001: 229). On the other hand, ideas do not play a very prominent role in LI, which is also recognized by Moravcsik when he writes that ‘[i]n the LI account of integration, ideas are present but not causally central. They may be irrelevant or random, or, more likely, they are “transmission belts” for interests' (Moravcsik, 2001: 229). The only reason why Moravcsik can correctly maintain that in LI ‘[s]ome national preferences ... are grounded in ideas' (1998: 23) is because some importance is ascribed to the latter in issue areas where the material consequences of policy initiatives are more or less impossible to calculate. For instance, he mentions ‘questions of European institutions and common foreign policy' as issues where governments/states will generally not to be under strong pressure from societal groups to pursue particular policies, which creates some room for government leaders to act on the basis of ‘ideologies and personal commitments' (Moravcsik, 1993: 494; see also Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig, 2009: 85).

According to Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig (2009: 76), ‘LI best explains policy-making in issue areas where social preferences are relatively certain and well defined'. In the core areas, like trade, agriculture and monetary policy, ideas are not assumed to influence preference formation at all. When it comes to ‘insignificant, exceptional and speculative issues' like those mentioned above or the Open Method of Coordination (ibid.: 85) where the preferences of societal groups are less clear and strong, and where the explanatory power of LI is thus recognised to be limited, ideas are conveniently allowed to play a role. To recapitulate, in LI no importance is ascribed to ideas in the explanation of what is (correctly) considered to be the ‘substantively important issues' (ibid.: 85) in the European integration process: here economic structures do the job alone. (3)

4. International bargains

Once the national preferences have been formulated, national decision-makers bring them to the intergovernmental bargaining table. At this second stage LI applies an intergovernmentalist bargaining theory in order to explain the outcome of negotiations. As the primary interest of the governments is to remain in office, they have a clear incentive to defend the national interest in the negotiation. Accordingly, ‘[t]he configuration of domestically determined national preferences defines a “bargaining space” of potentially viable agreements' (Moravcsik, 1993: 496-497). The outcome of a concrete negotiation, however, not only reflects the different national preferences but also the relative bargaining power of different states. Moravcsik defines power in terms of asymmetric interdependence: ‘Bargaining leverage stems most fundamentally from asymmetries in the relative intensity of national preferences, which reflect … the relative costs of agreements to remove negative externalities' (ibid.: 1993: 499). This means that ‘[t]he power of each government is inversely proportional to the relative value that it places on an agreement' (Moravcsik, 1998: 62).

How, then, is the agency-structure relationship dealt with at this second stage? Or to put it differently: how much freedom does government leaders have to pursue their own preferences or ideas (agency) and how much are they constrained by their context (structure)? First, the answer to this question depends on the issue area. As mentioned, governments are severely constrained by domestic societal groups in core areas: here they can only act within a narrow “bargaining space” which limits their freedom considerably. In more marginal (non-economic) issue areas this space widens and government leaders enjoy more freedom to pursue their own agendas. Second, any particular government is constrained by the bargaining spaces of other governments. The nature of these determines the extent to which a government leader is capable of realising national interests. Finally, the outcomes of previous bargains serve as the status quo ‘with respect to which societal actors and governments calculate preferences and alternatives to agreement' (Moravcsik, 1995: 612).

As mentioned above, the outcome of a concrete bargain reflects the relative bargaining power of each state. As bargaining power is defined in terms of asymmetric interdependence it is, in fact, derived from the very same structures as national preferences. These structures determine how attractive a potential policy is to societal groups - and thus governments - and consequently they also determine the relative bargaining power. Relative power is thus ultimately decided at the structural level - not at the level of agents. This brings us back to the point that was raised in the previous section, namely that the rationality assumption underpinning LI does not serve to render it an agency-centred theory. To be sure, there are plenty of agents in LI, and there is no denying that the theory belongs to the tradition of “methodological individualism”. But by substituting real agents with ‘calculating machines who always know what they want and are never uncertain about the future and even their own stakes and interests' (Risse, 2009: 147), LI effectively ends up with no notion of agency at all, at least not in its account of integration in core issue areas.

That it is apparently unnecessary to study the interaction between state representatives in order to explain the outcome of a bargain tells it all: the creativity, charisma, persuasiveness and negotiating abilities of particular agents are insignificant in LI. By assuming that agents are identical in the sense of being rational it is possible to derive the outcome of bargains simply by looking at the context in which it takes place. This makes LI a structuralist theory also in its second stage. To be sure, the structuralism of LI differs from conventional structuralism inasmuch as the former retains a focus on agents and their free choices. But the point is that the “methodological individualism” of LI and other rational choice theories does not entail a genuine notion of agency in that a free choice is neither free nor, indeed, a real choice, if it is always already given by the context in which the agent operates (see also Hay, 2002: 103-104; Tsebelis, 1990: 40). (4)

5. Institutional choice

Once governments have reached substantive agreement in a bargain, they set up institutional arrangements in order to secure it. At this third stage LI adopts a functional theory of institutional choice according to which governments pool or delegate authority in order to ‘constrain and control one another' (Moravcsik, 1998: 9). Authority is “pooled” when governments for instance agree to take decisions in an issue area by means of qualified majority voting in the Council, whereas “delegation” refers to the transfer of authority to more or less autonomous supranational institutions (ibid.: 1998: 67). Pooling and delegation are ‘viewed as solutions to the problem of “incomplete contracting,” which arises when member governments share broad goals but find it too costly or technically impossible to specify all future contingencies involved in legislating or enforcing those goals' (ibid.: 1998: 73).

By pooling or delegating, the credibility of the commitment to the substantive agreement that has been reached is enhanced. But by giving up authority in an issue area governments clearly run the risk of being either outvoted by other governments (pooling) or of being overruled by supranational institutions (delegation) in future cases. Hence, ‘[t]he specific level of pooling or delegation reflects a reciprocal cost-benefit analysis: governments renounce unilateral options in order to assure that all governments will coordinate their behavior in particular ways' (ibid.: 1998: 75). LI predicts that pooling and delegation will vary across issues and countries. Again, the preferences of societal groups are crucial: ‘Governments transfer sovereignty to commit other governments to accept policies favored by key domestic constituencies' (ibid.: 1998: 76). As accounted for above the preferences of societal groups are seen as structurally determined, at least in the core issue areas. In the end the governments' institutional choices thus become rather mechanical, following more or less automatically from the circumstances in which they are made.

According to LI, international institutions are ‘passive, transaction-cost reducing sets of rules' (Moravcsik, 1993: 508) that for instance serve to provide states with information ‘to reduce the states' uncertainty about each other's future preferences and behaviour' (Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig, 2009: 72). Somewhat surprisingly, Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig link the existence of such institutions to “unanticipated consequences” of actions, proclaiming that LI also assumes the existence of the latter:

‘If unanticipated consequences did not exist, there would be no need for international institutions to elaborate “incomplete contracts” to begin with'. The reason for institutions is precisely to elaborate agreements and credibly lock in compliance against defection by future unsatisfied governments' (2009: 75).

This, to be sure, is a somewhat unorthodox and problematic use of the concept. When, for instance, historical institutionalists are talking about unintended or unanticipated consequences in the context of European integration, their argument is that supranational institutions and policies tend to develop in ways not originally envisaged and subsequently not approved of by member state governments (Pierson, 1996). Due to “path dependency” and other mechanisms such institutions and the course of the integration process can become impossible for governments to control.

Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig clearly have something altogether different in mind when they talk about unanticipated consequences. In fact, what they are talking about can more accurately be denoted ‘anticipated but undesired outcomes'. These arise when rational governments anticipate that there is a risk that other rational governments will not comply with the substantive agreement that has been reached in an intergovernmental bargain. To avoid this undesired outcome governments agree on an institutional arrangement to create certainty. On this view, institutions (being ‘passive, transaction-cost reducing sets of rules') only contribute to minimise uncertainty by eliminating the risk of undesired outcomes (see also Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig, 2009: 72) - it is unthinkable that they can develop and behave in ways not intended by governments. At the end of the day, it is not unintended consequences that LI assumes the existence of but rather the ability of governments to very accurately predict the consequences of their substantive agreement and on this basis chose the most suitable institutional agreements. This dubious assumption can obviously only be made if it is held, as LI does, that agents are blessed with more or less perfect information, also of future outcomes of their actions (see also Pierson, 2004: 115-XXX).

6. What choice for Europe?

‘the motivations and coalitions underlying national preferences in specific decisions reflected the economic interest of sectors as predicted by their structural position in global markets … any feedback must take the form of changes in economic structures, not ideas' (Moravcsik, 1999b: 382)

The liberal intergovernmentalist explanation of regional integration ultimately comes down to developments in economic structures and it is therefore logical and appropriate that Moravcsik (1998: 501) refers to it as a ‘structural perspective'. Although the concept of “economic structures” is not defined as clearly as other LI concepts, it basically appears to denote the phenomena that economic indicators are expressions of, examples being trade flows, inflation rates, wealth and competitiveness. The method is thus to use economic indicators as expressions of the economic structures determining the preferences of agents. For instance it reads that

‘Taken together, capital mobility, trade flows, and inflationary convergence provide a prima facie explanation of the progressive shift in national preferences away from, then back toward, exchange-rate cooperation over the two decades following the collapse of the Bretton Woods. This period saw an increase in economic openness and, beginning in the late 1970s, convergence toward low inflation' (Moravcsik, 1998: 48)

But what caused this and other shifts in economic circumstances? What explains the timing of such shifts? Considering the enormous importance it ascribes to economic structures it would be completely reasonable to expect LI to address and tentatively provide a theoretical answer to such questions. But it doesn't! In all fairness, Moravcsik (1998: 48) does for instance pose the question of whether disinflation reflected ‘a change in economic ideas and ideology?' This is a by all means relevant question, especially as several studies, published both before and after The Choice for Europe, have documented how and why a neoliberal turn took place in this period (e.g. Overbeek, 1993; van Apeldoorn, 2002). This turn, which took the shape of a shift from Keynesian toward Monetarist ideas in the monetary area, was dialectically related to the disruption of the post-war class compromise between organised labour and national industrial capital, with the power balance shifting in favour of capital, especially transnationally oriented companies. More than anything else it was the institutionalisation of monetarist/neoliberal ideas in the course of the 1980s that brought about disinflation and caused a rise in cross-border trade flows and capital mobility (see e.g. Harris, 2006; Robinson, 2004).

Unfortunately, it would undermine the consistency (and parsimony) of LI if it allowed economic ideas to have a decisive impact on the transformation of economic structures - especially structures as important as capital mobility, trade flows, and inflation rates. As accounted for above it is shifts in these structures that, through the aggregated preferences of societal groups and interstate bargains, are to account for integration in the core issue areas that ‘LI best explains'. Hence, instead of attempting to answer his own question about the possible importance of a change in economic ideas, Moravcsik informs his readers that an analysis of the causes of disinflation ‘takes us beyond the scope of this book', adding that ‘[f]or our purposes it is essential only that convergence toward such norms was an exogenous factor' (1998: 48). Although this ‘exogenisation' of the causes of structural shifts is obviously a highly convenient move on part of Moravcsik, it is also a deeply unsatisfactory move that fundamentally invalidates the explanatory power of LI: integration is ultimately explained with changes in economic structures, but theoretical reflections on why and when such changes take place is simply missing.

Moravcsik and Schimmelfennig (2009: 68) proclaim that LI is a multi-causal framework that ‘rejects monocausal explanation'. Allegedly such explanations are avoided due to the fact that LI incorporates three theories, respectively explaining national preference formation, interstate bargains and institutional choice. However, it is doubtful whether this alone qualifies LI as a multi-causal theory. If the argument that has been advanced above is correct then LI is a theory (or a synthesis of theories) that explains regional integration as a mono-causal chain-reaction: it always starts with changes in economic structures; via societal groups these directly translate into national preferences/interests; the latter are brought into intergovernmental bargains; and the process always ends with an institutional choice (see 1). When economic structures change and a new chain-reaction is set in motion (at T1), institutional arrangements resulting from previous institutional choices serve as the status quo that is taken into consideration by societal groups and governments in their calculation of the costs and benefits of new integration initiatives. However, as Moravcsik conceptualises EC institutions ‘as a passive structure' and as ‘passive, transaction-cost reducing sets of rules' (1993: 508), they can hardly generate shifts in domestic preferences.

If mono-causality is avoided in LI it is thus merely in the narrow sense of it being not one but different economic structures (depending on the issue area) that determine agents' preferences and behaviour - as well as in the sense that ideas are allowed to play a role in less significant issue areas where economic incentives are unclear anyways. Either way, the relationship between economic structures and agents is conceptualised as a one-way street: structures determine and explain the behaviour of agents, whereas shifts in the economic structures are not explained. European integration is hereby presented as an essentially structure-driven process, as the one and only choice for Europe. Moreover, the liberal intergovernmentalist concept of structure is, as accounted for above, under-theorised. Consequently, LI ends up as an agent-centred theory almost devoid of agency while also being a structural deterministic theory lacking a genuinely theorised concept of structures and structural change.

7. The politics of Liberal Intergovernmentalism

‘Abstract discussions of competing modes of positivism, ideational causality, rationalist explanation, the relationship between agents and structures, often serve as principled excuses for not engaging in competitive theory testing. At the very least, such speculation expends a great deal of time, effort, and space that might have been devoted to the elaboration of concrete concepts, theories, hypotheses, and methods' (Moravcsik 1999a: 679)

In his various debates with constructivist scholars Moravcsik has made no secret of his general skepticism toward meta-theoretical reflections. He seems to take the view that such “speculation” should not take up the valuable time of social scientists. The latter, we are informed, employ ‘explicit social scientific methods … by clearly stating theories and hypotheses, the nature of alternative claims, and the nature of confirming and disconfirming evidence, ex ante. These skeptical practices render scholarly claims open to disconfirmation, either by one's own analysis or that of critics' (Moravcsik, 1999b: 389). The clear implication is that real social scientists are those who employ neo-positivist methods similar to the ones favoured by Moravcsik. There is no acknowledgement whatsoever that research produced in accordance with the methods and standards of other social science paradigms (say, constructivism or critical realism) might also qualify as being “social scientific”. Taking for granted that neo-positivist methods and standards are superior is, however, unwarranted. No other paradigm has been subjected to nearly as detailed and scathing criticism as (neo-)positivism has in the past couple of decades (see e.g. Bhaskar, 1986; Benton and Craib, 2001; Steinmetz, 2005). This extensive literature has apparently not impressed Moravcsik in the least: he doesn't discuss it anywhere, nor does it prevent him from criticising constructivists and reflectivists for failing to apply neo-positivist methods (Moravcsik, 1999; 2001). The latter are apparently beyond critique.

Moravcsik's narrow understanding of what counts as social scientific practice and what does not, conveniently gives him a carte blanche to disregard meta-theoretical reflections. This is convenient inasmuch as LI is based on dubious ontological assumptions which, in large part, follow as a consequence of the neo-positivist methods and standards informing it. To be sure, neo-positivism does not dictate that LI or any other theory must be structuralist and downplay the importance of agency and ideas. But it is certainly encouraged indirectly. One can only make clear predictions on the basis of theories that assume a high degree of regularity or orderliness in the social world or a specific part of it. Rational agents fit nicely into this universe because their behaviour is predictable once the structural incentives have been mapped. Reversely, if it is conceded that agents have different characteristics, inclinations and qualities and that a multitude of (moral, religious, nationalistic, cultural etc.) ideas and motives other than utility-maximisation inform their actions, then it also has to be conceded that it is impossible to predict how agents will act in a given situation merely by looking at their context. In short, the notion of agency does not resonate well with aspirations to construct parsimonious theories.

It is important to remember that theories are not merely politically neutral descriptions of social reality. As Cox (1981: 128) pointed out, there ‘is no such thing as theory in itself, divorced from a standpoint in time and space. When a theory so represents itself, it is the more important to examine it as ideology, and to lay bare its concealed perspective”. Albeit presented in neutral terms as a helpful ‘tool to bring the analyst closer to, really closer to ... historical reality' (Moravcsik, 1999b: 389), the perspective of LI is not objective or politically neutral. As Taylor (2008: XX) observes, albeit in a somewhat different context, ‘Moravcsik's theory of intergovernmentalism, involved a predetermined image of the end system, which made it difficult to detect the emergence of any other kind of system'. Indeed, LI is an inherently conservative perspective that serves to legitimise the existing type of integration in Europe and the neoliberal ideas that have shaped its course, especially after the mid-1980s. Among other things, neoliberalism prescribes that key institutions, such as central banks, should be separated from democratic accountability (Harvey, 2004: 66). In LI, where there is no mentioning of neoliberalist ideology and its social purpose, the “delegation” of power to supranational institutions with little democratic accountability is merely construed as a rational institutional choice, serving to enhance credible commitments (Moravcsik, 1998: 76). In continuation of this Moravcsik (2002) has even come out as a keen advocate of the EU's democratic deficit.

By seeking to explain regional integration by means of a few variables in a three-stage scheme that repeats itself over and over again, LI pictures a dynamic world as being essentially static. And it presents an in many respects dysfunctional political system (the EU) as being the by and large rational and thus natural choice for Europe. As other theories grounded in neo-positivism it hereby becomes ‘apt to provide scientific legitimacy for particular forms of political practice' (Wight, 2006: 8), namely practices serving to preserve the status quo. In the case of LI this is only exacerbated by the theory's structuralism and the ensuing lack of agency. LI does not only give scientific legitimacy to existing institutions and practices; by depriving agents of their agency it also sends the message that a significantly different system is unthinkable.

In Conclusion

In this article it has been examined how the relationship between agency and structure is dealt with in Andrew Moravcsik's LI. It can be concluded that what at first sight appears to be an agency-centred theory turns out to be a theory that, in the words of its own creator, can only ‘acknowledge a secondary role for ideas, feedback, and political agency in the integration process' (Moravcsik, 1999b: 388). In its account of integration in core issue areas LI is devoid of agency and ideas - here it all ultimately comes down to shifts in economic structures. Only in less significant areas, where the explanatory power of LI is held to be more limited, is the importance of ideas and political agency recognised. In other words, LI can rightly be regarded as a structuralist theory of integration. Having established this, the article went on to pose a crucial question that critics of LI have so far failed to ask due to their assumption that LI is an agency-centred theory: how does the theory explain shifts in the economic structures that dictate the preferences of societal groups? Unfortunately, the answer to the question is that LI does not explain them. Theoretical reflections on how, why and when structural shifts take place are left out of the theory. The theoretical gravity of this can hardly be exaggerated: explaining European integration in terms of structural shifts, the possible causes of which remain unaccounted for, amounts to not having explained that much at the end of the day.

Notes

(1) This approach is primarily associated with the “critical rationalism” of Karl R. Popper (e.g. Popper 1963) and Imre Lakatos' (1970) further developments of this position. Although Popper attacked traditional positivism, his own position is a revision, not a total rejection, of positivism. Hence, as Hindess (1977: 164-187) has suggested, Popper is in effect a neo-positivist.

(2) Some scholars have questioned whether Moravcsik actually delivers what he promises in this regard. Lieshout et al. (2004) have scrutinised the sources used in the important section of The Choice for Europe that deals with former French President de Gaulle's European policy (see Moravcsik 1998: 176-97), and find that ‘[o]nly 24 percent of the 221 references we have been able to check are unproblematic and fully correct' (2004: 116).

(3) In this respect LI is similar to other contemporary rational choice theories. To the extent they deal with ideas these merely constitute ‘a valuable supplement to interest-based, rational actor models' (Jacobsen 1995: 10). As in LI, ideas and preferences are for the most part considered to be separate variables.

(4) Morse makes a similar point in a discussion of neoclassical economics: ‘The economist's view of the person, as it now stands, is that the person is a pure stimulus-response machine. The preferences are given; the relative prices are given. The person is completely reactive. We might say that the person's behaviour is perfectly predetermined, or predestined, once the utility function has been formed. There presently is no scope within economics for the genuinely creative act, for the uniquely personal contribution' (1997: 182).

References

Benton, T. and I. Craib (2001) Philosophy of Social Science. The Philosophical Foundations of Social Thought, London and New York: Palgrave.

Bhaskar, R. (1986) Scientific Realism and Human Emancipation, London: Verso.

Bieler, A. and A.D. Morton (2001) ‘The Gordian Knot of Agency-Structure in International Relations: A Neo-Gramscian Perspective', European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 7, No. 1, pp. 5-35.

Caporaso, J.A. and J.T.S. Keeler (1995) ‘The European Union and Regional Integration Theory', in Rhodes, C. and Mazey, S. (eds.) The State of the European Union Volume 3: Building a European Polity?. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, pp. 29-62.

Christiansen, T. (1998) ‘‘Bringing process back in': the Longue Durée of European integration', Journal of European Integration, Vol. 21, pp. 99-121.

Christiansen, T., K.-E. Jørgensen and A. Wiener (2001) ‘The Social Construction of Europe', in Christiansen, T., Jørgensen, K.-E. and Wiener, A. (eds.) The Social Construction of Europe, London, Thousand Oaks, New Delhi: SAGE Publications.

Cini, M. (2007) ‘Intergovernmentalism', in M. Cini (ed.) European Union Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 99-116.

Cox, R.W. (1981) ‘Social Forces, States and World Order: Beyond International Relations', Millennium, Vol. 10, No. 2, pp. 126-155.

Dessler, D. (1989) 'What's at stake in the agent-structure debate?', International Organization, Vol. 43, No.3, pp. 441-473.

Diez, T. (1999) ‘Riding the AM-track through Europe; or, The Pitfalls of a Rationalist Journey Through European Integration', Millennium: Journal of International Studies, Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 355-369.

Doty, R.L. (1997) ‘Aporia: A Critical Exploration of the Agent-Structure Problematique in International Relations Theory', European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 3, No. 3, pp. 365-392.

Harris, J. (2006) The Dialectics of Globalization. Economic and Political Conflict in a Transnational World, Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

Harvey, D. (2004) A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hay, C. (2002) Political Analysis. A Critical Introduction, New York: Palgrave.

Hindess, B. (1977) Philosophy and Methodology in the Social Sciences, Sussex: The Harvester Press.

Hix, S. (1994) ‘The Study of the European Community: The Challenge to Comparative Politics', West European Politics, Vol 17, No. 1, January, pp. 1-30.

Hollis, M. and S. Smith (1990) Explaining and Understanding International Relations, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Jacobsen, J.K. (1995) ‘Much Ado about Ideas: The Cognitive Factors in Economic Policy', World Politics, Vol. 47, No. 1, pp. 283-320.

Lakatos, I. (1970) 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs', in Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Laursen, F. (2002) (ed.) The Amsterdam Treaty: National Preference Formation, Interstate Bargaining and Outcome, Odense: Odense University Press.

Lieshout, R.H, M.L.L Segers and A.M. van der Vleuten (2004) ‘De Gaulle, Moravcsik, and The Choice for Europe. Soft Sources,Weak Evidence', Journal of Cold War Studies, Vol. 6, No. 4, pp. 89-139.

McSweeney, B. (1998) ‘Moral Choice and European Integration', in McSweeney, B. (ed.) Moral Issues in International Affairs. Problems of European Integration. London: Macmillan, pp. 89-114.

Moravcsik, A. (1993) ‘Preferences and Power in the European Community: A Liberal Intergovernmentalist Approach', Journal of Common Market Studies, Vol. 31, No. 4, pp. 473-524.

Moravcsik, A. (1995) ‘Liberal Intergovernmentalism and Integration: A Rejoinder', Journal of Common Market Studies, Vol. 33, No. 4, December, pp. 611-628.

Moravcsik, A. (1997) ‘Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics', International Organization, Vol. 51, No. 4, Autumn, pp.513-553.

Moravcsik, A. (1998) The Choice for Europe: Social Purpose and State Power from Messina to Maastricht, New York: Cornell University Press.

Moravcsik, A. (1999a) ‘Is something rotten in the state of Denmark? Constructivism and European integration', Journal of European Public Policy, Vol. 6, No. 4, pp. 669-681.

Moravcsik, A. (1999b) ‘The Future of European Integration Studies: Social Science or Social Theory?', Millennium: Journal of International Studies, Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 371-391.

Moravcsik, A. (2001) in ‘A Constructivist Research Program in EU Studies', European Union Politics, Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 219-249.

Moravcsik, A. (2002) ‘In defence of the democratic deficit: reassessing legitimacy in the European Union', Journal of Common Market Studies, Vol. 40, No. 4, pp. 603-624.

Moravcsik, A. and F. Schimmelfennig (2009) ‘Liberal Intergovernmentalism', in Wiener, A. and T. Diez (eds.) European Integration Theory, 2nd edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 67-87.

Morse, J.R. (1997) ‘Who is Rational Economic Man?', Social Philosophy and Policy, Vol. 14, pp. 179-206.

Overbeek, H. (1993) (ed) Restructuring Hegemony in the Global Political Economy, London and New York: Routledge.

Pierson, P. (1996) ‘The Path to European Integration: A Historical Institutionalist Analysis', Comparative Political Studies, Vol. 29, No. 2, April, pp. 123-163.

Pierson, P. (2004) Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

Popper, K.R. (1963) ‘Science: Conjectures and Refutations', in Popper, K.R. Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Risse, T. (2004) ‘Social Constructivism and European Integration', in Wiener, A. and T. Diez (eds.) European Integration Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Risse, T. (2009) ‘Social Constructivism and European Integration', in Wiener, A. and T. Diez (eds.) European Integration Theory, 2nd edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 144-160.

Risse-Kappen, T. (1996) ‘Exploring the Nature of the Beast: International Relations Theory and Comparative Policy Analysis Meet the European Union', Journal of Common Market Studies, Vol. 34, No. 1, March, pp. 53-80.

Robinson, W.I. (2004) A Theory of Global Capitalism. Production, Class, and State in a Transnational World, Baltimore/London: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Steinmetz, G. (2005) (ed.) The Politics of Method in the Human Sciences. Positivism and its Epistemological Others, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Taylor, P. (2008) The End of European Integration: Anti-Europeanism Examined, London and New York: Routledge.

Tsebelis, G. (1990) Nested Games. Rational Choice in Comparative Politics, Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press.

Van Apeldoorn, B. (2002) Transnational Capitalism and the Struggle Over European Integration, London and New York: Routledge.

Wendt, A. (1987) ‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory', International Organization, Vol. 41, No. 3, Summer, pp. 335-370.

Wight, C. (2006) Agents, Structures and International Relations. Politics as Ontology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wincott, D. (1995) ‘Institutional Interaction and European Integration: Towards an Everyday Critique of Liberal Intergovernmentalism', Journal of Common Market Studies, Vol. 33, No. 4, December, pp. 597-609.

Wind, M. (2001) Sovereignty and European Integration. Towards a Post-Hobbesian Order, New York: Palgrave.




rev

Our Service Portfolio

jb

Want To Place An Order Quickly?

Then shoot us a message on Whatsapp, WeChat or Gmail. We are available 24/7 to assist you.

whatsapp

Do not panic, you are at the right place

jb

Visit Our essay writting help page to get all the details and guidence on availing our assiatance service.

Get 20% Discount, Now
£19 £14/ Per Page
14 days delivery time

Our writting assistance service is undoubtedly one of the most affordable writting assistance services and we have highly qualified professionls to help you with your work. So what are you waiting for, click below to order now.

Get An Instant Quote

ORDER TODAY!

Our experts are ready to assist you, call us to get a free quote or order now to get succeed in your academics writing.

Get a Free Quote Order Now